52. Exchangeability and Bayesian Updating#
Contents
52.1. Overview#
This lecture studies learning via Bayes’ Law.
We touch foundations of Bayesian statistical inference invented by Bruno DeFinetti [de Finetti, 1937].
The relevance of DeFinetti’s work for economists is presented forcefully in chapter 11 of [Kreps, 1988] by David Kreps.
An example that we study in this lecture is a key component of this lecture that augments the classic job search model of McCall [McCall, 1970] by presenting an unemployed worker with a statistical inference problem.
Here we create graphs that illustrate the role that a likelihood ratio plays in Bayes’ Law.
We’ll use such graphs to provide insights into mechanics driving outcomes in this lecture about learning in an augmented McCall job search model.
Among other things, this lecture discusses connections between the statistical concepts of sequences of random variables that are
independently and identically distributed
exchangeable (also known as conditionally independently and identically distributed)
Understanding these concepts is essential for appreciating how Bayesian updating works.
You can read about exchangeability here.
Because another term for exchangeable is conditionally independent, we want to convey an answer to the question conditional on what?
We also tell why an assumption of independence precludes learning while an assumption of conditional independence makes learning possible.
Below, we’ll often use
\(W\) to denote a random variable
\(w\) to denote a particular realization of a random variable \(W\)
Let’s start with some imports:
import matplotlib.pyplot as plt
plt.rcParams["figure.figsize"] = (11, 5) #set default figure size
from numba import jit, vectorize
from math import gamma
import scipy.optimize as op
from scipy.integrate import quad
import numpy as np
52.2. Independently and Identically Distributed#
We begin by looking at the notion of an independently and identically distributed sequence of random variables.
An independently and identically distributed sequence is often abbreviated as IID.
Two notions are involved
independence
identically distributed
A sequence \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is independently distributed if the joint probability density of the sequence is the product of the densities of the components of the sequence.
The sequence \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is independently and identically distributed (IID) if in addition the marginal density of \(W_t\) is the same for all \(t =0, 1, \ldots\).
For example, let \(p(W_0, W_1, \ldots)\) be the joint density of the sequence and let \(p(W_t)\) be the marginal density for a particular \(W_t\) for all \(t =0, 1, \ldots\).
Then the joint density of the sequence \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is IID if
so that the joint density is the product of a sequence of identical marginal densities.
52.2.1. IID Means Past Observations Don’t Tell Us Anything About Future Observations#
If a sequence is random variables is IID, past information provides no information about future realizations.
Therefore, there is nothing to learn from the past about the future.
To understand these statements, let the joint distribution of a sequence of random variables \(\{W_t\}_{t=0}^T\) that is not necessarily IID be
Using the laws of probability, we can always factor such a joint density into a product of conditional densities:
In general,
which states that the conditional density on the left side does not equal the marginal density on the right side.
But in the special IID case,
and partial history \(W_{t-1}, \ldots, W_0\) contains no information about the probability of \(W_t\).
So in the IID case, there is nothing to learn about the densities of future random variables from past random variables.
But when the sequence is not IID, there is something to learn about the future from observations of past random variables.
We turn next to an instance of the general case in which the sequence is not IID.
Please watch for what can be learned from the past and when.
52.3. A Setting in Which Past Observations Are Informative#
Let \(\{W_t\}_{t=0}^\infty\) be a sequence of nonnegative scalar random variables with a joint probability distribution constructed as follows.
There are two distinct cumulative distribution functions \(F\) and \(G\) that have densities \(f\) and \(g\), respectively, for a nonnegative scalar random variable \(W\).
Before the start of time, say at time \(t= -1\), “nature” once and for all selects either \(f\) or \(g\).
Thereafter at each time \(t \geq 0\), nature draws a random variable \(W_t\) from the selected distribution.
So the data are permanently generated as independently and identically distributed (IID) draws from either \(F\) or \(G\).
We could say that objectively, meaning after nature has chosen either \(F\) or \(G\), the probability that the data are generated as draws from \(F\) is either \(0\) or \(1\).
We now drop into this setting a partially informed decision maker who knows
both \(F\) and \(G\), but
not the \(F\) or \(G\) that nature drew once-and-for-all at \(t = -1\)
So our decision maker does not know which of the two distributions nature selected.
The decision maker describes his ignorance with a subjective probability \(\tilde \pi\) and reasons as if nature had selected \(F\) with probability \(\tilde \pi \in (0,1)\) and \(G\) with probability \(1 - \tilde \pi\).
Thus, we assume that the decision maker
knows both \(F\) and \(G\)
doesn’t know which of these two distributions that nature has drawn
expresses his ignorance by acting as if or thinking that nature chose distribution \(F\) with probability \(\tilde \pi \in (0,1)\) and distribution \(G\) with probability \(1 - \tilde \pi\)
at date \(t \geq 0\) knows the partial history \(w_t, w_{t-1}, \ldots, w_0\)
To proceed, we want to know the decision maker’s belief about the joint distribution of the partial history.
We’ll discuss that next and in the process describe the concept of exchangeability.
52.4. Relationship Between IID and Exchangeable#
Conditional on nature selecting \(F\), the joint density of the sequence \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is
Conditional on nature selecting \(G\), the joint density of the sequence \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is
Thus, conditional on nature having selected \(F\), the sequence \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is independently and identically distributed.
Furthermore, conditional on nature having selected \(G\), the sequence \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is also independently and identically distributed.
But what about the unconditional distribution of a partial history?
The unconditional distribution of \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is evidently
Under the unconditional distribution \(h(W_0, W_1, \ldots )\), the sequence \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is not independently and identically distributed.
To verify this claim, it is sufficient to notice, for example, that
Thus, the conditional distribution
This means that random variable \(W_0\) contains information about random variable \(W_1\).
So there is something to learn from the past about the future.
But what and how?
52.5. Exchangeability#
While the sequence \(W_0, W_1, \ldots\) is not IID, it can be verified that it is exchangeable, which means that the ``re-ordered’’ joint distributions \(h(W_0, W_1)\) and \(h(W_1, W_0)\) satisfy
and so on.
More generally, a sequence of random variables is said to be exchangeable if the joint probability distribution for a sequence does not change when the positions in the sequence in which finitely many of random variables appear are altered.
Equation (52.1) represents our instance of an exchangeable joint density over a sequence of random variables as a mixture of two IID joint densities over a sequence of random variables.
For a Bayesian statistician, the mixing parameter \(\tilde \pi \in (0,1)\) has a special interpretation as a subjective prior probability that nature selected probability distribution \(F\).
DeFinetti [de Finetti, 1937] established a related representation of an exchangeable process created by mixing sequences of IID Bernoulli random variables with parameter \(\theta \in (0,1)\) and mixing probability density \(\pi(\theta)\) that a Bayesian statistician would interpret as a prior over the unknown Bernoulli parameter \(\theta\).
52.6. Bayes’ Law#
We noted above that in our example model there is something to learn about about the future from past data drawn from our particular instance of a process that is exchangeable but not IID.
But how can we learn?
And about what?
The answer to the about what question is \(\tilde \pi\).
The answer to the how question is to use Bayes’ Law.
Another way to say use Bayes’ Law is to say from a (subjective) joint distribution, compute an appropriate conditional distribution.
Let’s dive into Bayes’ Law in this context.
Let \(q\) represent the distribution that nature actually draws \(w\) from and let
where we regard \(\pi\) as a decision maker’s subjective probability (also called a personal probability).
Suppose that at \(t \geq 0\), the decision maker has observed a history \(w^t \equiv [w_t, w_{t-1}, \ldots, w_0]\).
We let
where we adopt the convention
The distribution of \(w_{t+1}\) conditional on \(w^t\) is then
Bayes’ rule for updating \(\pi_{t+1}\) is
Equation (52.2) follows from Bayes’ rule, which tells us that
where
52.7. More Details about Bayesian Updating#
Let’s stare at and rearrange Bayes’ Law as represented in equation (52.2) with the aim of understanding how the posterior probability \(\pi_{t+1}\) is influenced by the prior probability \(\pi_t\) and the likelihood ratio
It is convenient for us to rewrite the updating rule (52.2) as
This implies that
Notice how the likelihood ratio and the prior interact to determine whether an observation \(w_{t+1}\) leads the decision maker to increase or decrease the subjective probability he/she attaches to distribution \(F\).
When the likelihood ratio \(l(w_{t+1})\) exceeds one, the observation \(w_{t+1}\) nudges the probability \(\pi\) put on distribution \(F\) upward, and when the likelihood ratio \(l(w_{t+1})\) is less that one, the observation \(w_{t+1}\) nudges \(\pi\) downward.
Representation (52.3) is the foundation of some graphs that we’ll use to display the dynamics of \(\{\pi_t\}_{t=0}^\infty\) that are induced by Bayes’ Law.
We’ll plot \(l\left(w\right)\) as a way to enlighten us about how learning – i.e., Bayesian updating of the probability \(\pi\) that nature has chosen distribution \(f\) – works.
To create the Python infrastructure to do our work for us, we construct a wrapper function that displays informative graphs given parameters of \(f\) and \(g\).
@vectorize
def p(x, a, b):
"The general beta distribution function."
r = gamma(a + b) / (gamma(a) * gamma(b))
return r * x ** (a-1) * (1 - x) ** (b-1)
def learning_example(F_a=1, F_b=1, G_a=3, G_b=1.2):
"""
A wrapper function that displays the updating rule of belief π,
given the parameters which specify F and G distributions.
"""
f = jit(lambda x: p(x, F_a, F_b))
g = jit(lambda x: p(x, G_a, G_b))
# l(w) = f(w) / g(w)
l = lambda w: f(w) / g(w)
# objective function for solving l(w) = 1
obj = lambda w: l(w) - 1
x_grid = np.linspace(0, 1, 100)
π_grid = np.linspace(1e-3, 1-1e-3, 100)
w_max = 1
w_grid = np.linspace(1e-12, w_max-1e-12, 100)
# the mode of beta distribution
# use this to divide w into two intervals for root finding
G_mode = (G_a - 1) / (G_a + G_b - 2)
roots = np.empty(2)
roots[0] = op.root_scalar(obj, bracket=[1e-10, G_mode]).root
roots[1] = op.root_scalar(obj, bracket=[G_mode, 1-1e-10]).root
fig, (ax1, ax2, ax3) = plt.subplots(1, 3, figsize=(18, 5))
ax1.plot(l(w_grid), w_grid, label='$l$', lw=2)
ax1.vlines(1., 0., 1., linestyle="--")
ax1.hlines(roots, 0., 2., linestyle="--")
ax1.set_xlim([0., 2.])
ax1.legend(loc=4)
ax1.set(xlabel='$l(w)=f(w)/g(w)$', ylabel='$w$')
ax2.plot(f(x_grid), x_grid, label='$f$', lw=2)
ax2.plot(g(x_grid), x_grid, label='$g$', lw=2)
ax2.vlines(1., 0., 1., linestyle="--")
ax2.hlines(roots, 0., 2., linestyle="--")
ax2.legend(loc=4)
ax2.set(xlabel='$f(w), g(w)$', ylabel='$w$')
area1 = quad(f, 0, roots[0])[0]
area2 = quad(g, roots[0], roots[1])[0]
area3 = quad(f, roots[1], 1)[0]
ax2.text((f(0) + f(roots[0])) / 4, roots[0] / 2, f"{area1: .3g}")
ax2.fill_between([0, 1], 0, roots[0], color='blue', alpha=0.15)
ax2.text(np.mean(g(roots)) / 2, np.mean(roots), f"{area2: .3g}")
w_roots = np.linspace(roots[0], roots[1], 20)
ax2.fill_betweenx(w_roots, 0, g(w_roots), color='orange', alpha=0.15)
ax2.text((f(roots[1]) + f(1)) / 4, (roots[1] + 1) / 2, f"{area3: .3g}")
ax2.fill_between([0, 1], roots[1], 1, color='blue', alpha=0.15)
W = np.arange(0.01, 0.99, 0.08)
Π = np.arange(0.01, 0.99, 0.08)
ΔW = np.zeros((len(W), len(Π)))
ΔΠ = np.empty((len(W), len(Π)))
for i, w in enumerate(W):
for j, π in enumerate(Π):
lw = l(w)
ΔΠ[i, j] = π * (lw / (π * lw + 1 - π) - 1)
q = ax3.quiver(Π, W, ΔΠ, ΔW, scale=2, color='r', alpha=0.8)
ax3.fill_between(π_grid, 0, roots[0], color='blue', alpha=0.15)
ax3.fill_between(π_grid, roots[0], roots[1], color='green', alpha=0.15)
ax3.fill_between(π_grid, roots[1], w_max, color='blue', alpha=0.15)
ax3.hlines(roots, 0., 1., linestyle="--")
ax3.set(xlabel='$\pi$', ylabel='$w$')
ax3.grid()
plt.show()
<>:78: SyntaxWarning: invalid escape sequence '\p'
<>:78: SyntaxWarning: invalid escape sequence '\p'
/tmp/ipykernel_2138/3701171347.py:78: SyntaxWarning: invalid escape sequence '\p'
ax3.set(xlabel='$\pi$', ylabel='$w$')
Now we’ll create a group of graphs that illustrate dynamics induced by Bayes’ Law.
We’ll begin with Python function default values of various objects, then change them in a subsequent example.
learning_example()
Please look at the three graphs above created for an instance in which \(f\) is a uniform distribution on \([0,1]\) (i.e., a Beta distribution with parameters \(F_a=1, F_b=1\)), while \(g\) is a Beta distribution with the default parameter values \(G_a=3, G_b=1.2\).
The graph on the left plots the likelihood ratio \(l(w)\) as the absciassa axis against \(w\) as the ordinate.
The middle graph plots both \(f(w)\) and \(g(w)\) against \(w\), with the horizontal dotted lines showing values of \(w\) at which the likelihood ratio equals \(1\).
The graph on the right plots arrows to the right that show when Bayes’ Law makes \(\pi\) increase and arrows to the left that show when Bayes’ Law make \(\pi\) decrease.
Lengths of the arrows show magnitudes of the force from Bayes’ Law impelling \(\pi\) to change.
These lengths depend on both the prior probability \(\pi\) on the abscissa axis and the evidence in the form of the current draw of \(w\) on the ordinate axis.
The fractions in the colored areas of the middle graphs are probabilities under \(F\) and \(G\), respectively, that realizations of \(w\) fall into the interval that updates the belief \(\pi\) in a correct direction (i.e., toward \(0\) when \(G\) is the true distribution, and toward \(1\) when \(F\) is the true distribution).
For example, in the above example, under true distribution \(F\), \(\pi\) will be updated toward \(0\) if \(w\) falls into the interval \([0.524, 0.999]\), which occurs with probability \(1 - .524 = .476\) under \(F\).
But this would occur with probability \(0.816\) if \(G\) were the true distribution.
The fraction \(0.816\) in the orange region is the integral of \(g(w)\) over this interval.
Next we use our code to create graphs for another instance of our model.
We keep \(F\) the same as in the preceding instance, namely a uniform distribution, but now assume that \(G\) is a Beta distribution with parameters \(G_a=2, G_b=1.6\).
learning_example(G_a=2, G_b=1.6)
Notice how the likelihood ratio, the middle graph, and the arrows compare with the previous instance of our example.
52.8. Appendix#
52.8.1. Sample Paths of \(\pi_t\)#
Now we’ll have some fun by plotting multiple realizations of sample paths of \(\pi_t\) under two possible assumptions about nature’s choice of distribution, namely
that nature permanently draws from \(F\)
that nature permanently draws from \(G\)
Outcomes depend on a peculiar property of likelihood ratio processes discussed in this lecture.
To proceed, we create some Python code.
def function_factory(F_a=1, F_b=1, G_a=3, G_b=1.2):
# define f and g
f = jit(lambda x: p(x, F_a, F_b))
g = jit(lambda x: p(x, G_a, G_b))
@jit
def update(a, b, π):
"Update π by drawing from beta distribution with parameters a and b"
# Draw
w = np.random.beta(a, b)
# Update belief
π = 1 / (1 + ((1 - π) * g(w)) / (π * f(w)))
return π
@jit
def simulate_path(a, b, T=50):
"Simulates a path of beliefs π with length T"
π = np.empty(T+1)
# initial condition
π[0] = 0.5
for t in range(1, T+1):
π[t] = update(a, b, π[t-1])
return π
def simulate(a=1, b=1, T=50, N=200, display=True):
"Simulates N paths of beliefs π with length T"
π_paths = np.empty((N, T+1))
if display:
fig = plt.figure()
for i in range(N):
π_paths[i] = simulate_path(a=a, b=b, T=T)
if display:
plt.plot(range(T+1), π_paths[i], color='b', lw=0.8, alpha=0.5)
if display:
plt.show()
return π_paths
return simulate
simulate = function_factory()
We begin by generating \(N\) simulated \(\{\pi_t\}\) paths with \(T\) periods when the sequence is truly IID draws from \(F\). We set an initial prior \(\pi_{-1} = .5\).
T = 50
# when nature selects F
π_paths_F = simulate(a=1, b=1, T=T, N=1000)
In the above example, for most paths \(\pi_t \rightarrow 1\).
So Bayes’ Law evidently eventually discovers the truth for most of our paths.
Next, we generate paths with \(T\) periods when the sequence is truly IID draws from \(G\). Again, we set the initial prior \(\pi_{-1} = .5\).
# when nature selects G
π_paths_G = simulate(a=3, b=1.2, T=T, N=1000)
In the above graph we observe that now most paths \(\pi_t \rightarrow 0\).
52.8.2. Rates of convergence#
We study rates of convergence of \(\pi_t\) to \(1\) when nature generates the data as IID draws from \(F\) and of convergence of \(\pi_t\) to \(0\) when nature generates IID draws from \(G\).
We do this by averaging across simulated paths of \(\{\pi_t\}_{t=0}^T\).
Using \(N\) simulated \(\pi_t\) paths, we compute \(1 - \sum_{i=1}^{N}\pi_{i,t}\) at each \(t\) when the data are generated as draws from \(F\) and compute \(\sum_{i=1}^{N}\pi_{i,t}\) when the data are generated as draws from \(G\).
plt.plot(range(T+1), 1 - np.mean(π_paths_F, 0), label='F generates')
plt.plot(range(T+1), np.mean(π_paths_G, 0), label='G generates')
plt.legend()
plt.title("convergence");
From the above graph, rates of convergence appear not to depend on whether \(F\) or \(G\) generates the data.
52.8.3. Graph of Ensemble Dynamics of \(\pi_t\)#
More insights about the dynamics of \(\{\pi_t\}\) can be gleaned by computing conditional expectations of \(\frac{\pi_{t+1}}{\pi_{t}}\) as functions of \(\pi_t\) via integration with respect to the pertinent probability distribution:
where \(a =f,g\).
The following code approximates the integral above:
def expected_ratio(F_a=1, F_b=1, G_a=3, G_b=1.2):
# define f and g
f = jit(lambda x: p(x, F_a, F_b))
g = jit(lambda x: p(x, G_a, G_b))
l = lambda w: f(w) / g(w)
integrand_f = lambda w, π: f(w) * l(w) / (π * l(w) + 1 - π)
integrand_g = lambda w, π: g(w) * l(w) / (π * l(w) + 1 - π)
π_grid = np.linspace(0.02, 0.98, 100)
expected_rario = np.empty(len(π_grid))
for q, inte in zip(["f", "g"], [integrand_f, integrand_g]):
for i, π in enumerate(π_grid):
expected_rario[i]= quad(inte, 0, 1, args=(π,))[0]
plt.plot(π_grid, expected_rario, label=f"{q} generates")
plt.hlines(1, 0, 1, linestyle="--")
plt.xlabel("$π_t$")
plt.ylabel("$E[\pi_{t+1}/\pi_t]$")
plt.legend()
plt.show()
<>:21: SyntaxWarning: invalid escape sequence '\p'
<>:21: SyntaxWarning: invalid escape sequence '\p'
/tmp/ipykernel_2138/2337625297.py:21: SyntaxWarning: invalid escape sequence '\p'
plt.ylabel("$E[\pi_{t+1}/\pi_t]$")
First, consider the case where \(F_a=F_b=1\) and \(G_a=3, G_b=1.2\).
expected_ratio()
The above graphs shows that when \(F\) generates the data, \(\pi_t\) on average always heads north, while when \(G\) generates the data, \(\pi_t\) heads south.
Next, we’ll look at a degenerate case in whcih \(f\) and \(g\) are identical beta distributions, and \(F_a=G_a=3, F_b=G_b=1.2\).
In a sense, here there is nothing to learn.
expected_ratio(F_a=3, F_b=1.2)
The above graph says that \(\pi_t\) is inert and remains at its initial value.
Finally, let’s look at a case in which \(f\) and \(g\) are neither very different nor identical, in particular one in which \(F_a=2, F_b=1\) and \(G_a=3, G_b=1.2\).
expected_ratio(F_a=2, F_b=1, G_a=3, G_b=1.2)
52.9. Sequels#
We’ll apply and dig deeper into some of the ideas presented in this lecture:
this lecture describes likelihood ratio processes and their role in frequentist and Bayesian statistical theories
this lecture studies whether a World War II US Navy Captain’s hunch that a (frequentist) decision rule that the Navy had told him to use was inferior to a sequential rule that Abraham Wald had not yet designed.